Friday 18 June 2010

Review of "Metametaphysics"

This Review of Metametaphysics by Guido Imaguire is of a book collecting 17 contributions on that topic, edited by Chalmers, Manley and Wasserman.

The authors apparently form two opposing camps representing various degrees of "deflationism" or "anti-deflationism" (among other terms), and this therefore represents one of the many contemporary debates whose novelty consists partly in their not rejecting out of hand Carnap's position on metaphysics.

WIthout having read the review fully, let alone the book, I am given the impression of a menagerie.

At the beginning of the twentieth century philosophers were aware of their vulnerability.  Russell's metaphysics was savaged by Wittgenstein, and he promptly abandoned metaphysics, imagining that Wittgenstein was the man for the job.  Wittgenstein however, possibly impressed by how easy it is for a young kid to wreak havock with the metaphysical pretensions of a great figure like Russell, decided instead to concoct a philosophy the principle feature of which is to say nothing sufficiently definite ever to be refuted.

Though not fond of metaphysics, Carnap's did not shy from the kind of ambitious philosophical program which carried risk of failure, and was subjected to devastating attack mid century by representatives of an emerging sense of self confidence in American academic philosophy.

From those days of vulnerability we seem to have moved in the second half to a pluralism of philosophical standpoint which admitted almost anything which could not be confused with the standard caricature of the only philosophical veiwpoint held to have been definitively refuted (i.e. that of Carnap).

Have philosophers become irrefutable?
Do they now engage only in works of fantasy which cannot be dismissed on the ground that they speak only of an abstract realm which bears no relation to reality (even when it discusses realism)?

Like Carnap, I am a pluralist, now not only a linguistic pluralist but a methodological one.   But Carnap and myself are not idle fantasists.
Though we would not deny anyone the language of their choice, we like to adopt languages and methods on a pragmatic basis, and an undue proliferation of languages, or of metaphyics, probably will not provide a basis for any great advance in our knowledge either scientific or philosophical.

What then might constitute and undue proliferation?

Fortunately I do not need to answer that question.
The onus is on those who propose to motivate their proposal, and on those who adopt to select carefully for their purposes in hand.

What we still lack, which Carnap tried to supply but was rebuffed, was any way of sorting out the philosophical chaff from the real money.
The tools of modern logic were thought to supply the means to make that distinction, and though they may fall short of the whole task, philosophers have never come near exploiting them to the extent envisaged by Carnap.

Until these questions of analytic method are reconsidered and philosophy begins to be undertaken rigorously wherever that is feasible, we will be able to look upon such a collection and wonder whether the debate it represents can ever yield fruit.

RBJ

2 comments:

  1. What an excellent piece, Roger, which I would even describe as a manifesto.

    I would add the name of Popper. I mean: having learned some of the big names of philosophy, even analytic philosophy, in the twentieth-century, perhaps a bit about that 'fear of risk' or lack of it can be related to his views on 'falsificationism'.

    The picture by the time of the early Ayer, say, in his "Language, Truth, and Logic", was that a philosophical standpoint was NOT a standpoint about the world. I mean: HE was a character! He would allow the legitimacy of a 'formal' standpoint as represented by pure logic, but anything more substantive was held to be not legitimate. Himself, he spent the next decates writing on the foundations of empirical knowledge -- from a philosophical perspective -- and it's not clear HOW that counted as legitimate by his earlier canons. His charming attitude to 'verifiability by principle' and such filled the pages of much of the philosophy journal literature at the time. And then... Popper. His emphasis on falsifiability, rather, emphasised in an even stronger way the idea of 'risk-taking' you are referring to. He proposed that, notably, as an alternate to confirmability and inductivism. And he went slightly order. He did not mean 'falsifiability' as a demarcation of 'meaning' (as I think he expressed it) but a demarcation between 'Science' and anything else ('pseudo-science'). I think that anyone taking Popper's grand proclamations at the time, if a philosopher, would have to have reflected on what it means to take a risk as far as philosophy goes. -- Of course, Quine did not help with his attack on analyticity -- but the replies to his views (explicit, as in Grice, or implicit as in Carnap with his continued work) -- showed a way in which also Popper's facile dichotomies could be challenged. From there to deflationist metaphysics and the full menagerie is just a stone's throw!

    ReplyDelete
  2. Hi, Rudolph. Greetings from an old colleague:
    http://ottoneurathsboat.blogspot.com/

    ReplyDelete